Showing posts with label cita. Show all posts
Showing posts with label cita. Show all posts

Tuesday, 18 October 2011

La Arquitectura (G. W. F. Hegel)

"Así pues, podemos asignar al sistema de las artes particulares la siguiente división: 

 El primer puesto corresponde, por la naturaleza misma de las cosas, a la arquitectura. Representa los inicios del arte, pues en sus inicios el arte todavía no ha hallado, para la representación de su contenido espiritual, los materiales apropiados ni las formas correspondientes, lo cual le obliga a limitarse a la simple busqueda de la verdadera adecuación y a contentarse con un contenido y un modo de representación puramente exteriores. 

Los materiales con que trabaja este primer arte estan desprovistos de espiritualidad: se trata de la pesada materia sometida a las leyes de la gravedad; en cuanto a la forma, consiste en reunir de modo regular y simétrico las formaciones de la naturaleza exterior, en realizar la totalidad de una obra de arte haciendo de ella simple reflejo del espíritu."





Tuesday, 15 March 2011

La belleza no es lo que era (J. Fernandez Vega)

Publicado en antrposmoderno.com el 2005-04-05; citado en colaboratorioarte.com

El gesto vanguardista de Marcel Duchamp, al exponer un mingitorio como obra de arte, asestó un golpe mortal al anhelo de belleza que la humanidad creía implícito en toda expresión artística. Desacreditada, ridiculizada como ideal burgués o decadente, la belleza se tomó venganza invadiéndolo todo: la moda, la publicidad, el diseño y cada rincón de la vida cotidiana. Como dice Umberto Eco en su reciente “Historia de la belleza”, nuestra época se rindió “a la orgía de la tolerancia, al imparable politeísmo de la belleza”. ¿Es posible aún hallar un criterio sobre qué es lo bello y lo feo en el arte?

Una historia de la belleza se puede transformar con mucha facilidad en una historia del mundo, sin que ello implique, por supuesto, que ni ese mundo ni esa historia hayan sido especialmente bellos. Más bien significa que a lo largo de épocas, y de muy distinta manera en cada una, la belleza ha sido un propósito persistente y un anhelo profundo. Desde la decoración del hogar, del palacio o del templo hasta el encuentro amoroso entre las personas pasando por el éxtasis ante las maravillas de la naturaleza estuvieron gobernados por un deseo de belleza. Sin olvidar por cierto lo que hoy llamaríamos formas estéticas, las cuales contribuyeron a definir la identidad de cada momento del pasado humano.

Pero en la actualidad la idea de belleza parece haber perdido el venerable, indiscutido arraigo del que gozó durante la mayor parte de la historia. Las vanguardias artísticas del siglo XX pusieron en crisis su vigencia, su carácter homogéneo y reconocible, incluso dejaron de aspirar a ella. La marginaron y la ridiculizaron. Pocas nociones se hallan tan asociadas a nuestra idea convencional del arte como la de belleza; pocas, sin embargo, se encuentran tan a menudo alejadas de nuestra experiencia habitual del arte contemporáneo. ¿Cómo se llegó a este agudo contraste?

Seguir leyendo

Sunday, 24 October 2010

The Aesthetics of Architecture (R. Scruton)

"It is essential to distinguish architectural aesthetics, as I conceive it, from something else that sometimes goes by the same name, but which one might call, for clarity's sake, architectural theory. Architectural theory consists in the attempt to formulate the maxims, rules and precepts which govern, or ought to govern, the practice of the builder. For example, the classical theory of the Orders, as it is found in the great treatises of Vitruvius, Alberti, Serlio and Vignola, which lays down rules for the systematic combination and ornamentation of the parts of a building, belongs to architectural theory; so too do most of the precepts contained in Ruskin's The Stones of Venice and Seven Lamps. Such precepts assume that we already know what we are seeking to achieve: the nature of architectural success is not at issue; the question is, rather, how best to achieve it. A theory of architecture impinges on aesthetics only if it claims a universal validity, for then it must aim to capture the essence, and not the accidents, of architectural beauty. But such a theory is implicitly philosophical, and must be judged accordingly; we will wish to know whether it succeeds in establishing its claims a priori, by a consideration of the phenomena in their most abstract and universal guise. As a matter of fact it has been characteristic of architectural theorists, from Vitruvius to Le Corbusier, to claim this universal validity for their laws. And no architectural aesthetics can leave such claims untouched. Vitruvius, Alberti,  Ruskin and Le Corbusier cannot all be right in believing that their favoured form of architecture is uniquely authorized by the rational understanding. As we shall see, they are all wrong.


It may still be thought that there is no real subject of architectural, as opposed to general, aesthetics. If philosophy is to be as abstract as I claim it is, ought it not to consider the aesthetic experience in its full generality, in isolation from the accidental constraints imposed by particular art forms and particular conceptions of success? Why is there any special need for a philosophy of architecture, other than the purely ephemeral one, that architecture is misunderstood by so many of its present practitioners? Is there not one and the same concept of beauty employed in the discussion of poetry, music, painting and building, and is there not one single faculty involved in the appreciation of all those arts? Once we have made the distinction between architectural aesthetics and architectural theory it may seem that little remains to the former other than the delineation of abstractions that have no special application to the practice of the architect. And it is certainly true that philosophers have approached the subject of aesthetics as though it could find expression only in such comprehensive abstractions, and could make none but passing and inessential references to the individual forms of art.

Now as a matter of fact architecture presents an immediate problem for any such general philosophical theory of aesthetic interest. Through its impersonal and at the same time functional qualities architecture stands apart from the other arts, seeming to require quite peculiar attitudes, not only for its creation, but also for its enjoyment. Generalized theories of aesthetic interest, such as those of Kant and Schopenhauer, tend to give rather odd accounts of architecture, and those philosophers who have treated the problem seriously - among whom Hegel is perhaps the most prominent - have often described the appreciation of architecture in terms inappropriate to the other forms of art. For Hegel, for example, architecture was a medium only half articulate, unable to give full expression to the Idea, and hence relegated to the level of pure symbolism, from which it must be redeemed by statuary and ornament. 

It is not difficult to see why Hegel should have thought that. It is natural to suppose that representational arts, such as painting, drama, poetry and sculpture, give rise to an interest unlike the interest aroused by such abstract arts as music and architecture. But it is also natural to suppose that music has expressive, sensuous and dramatic powers in common with the representational arts. Only architecture seems to stand wholly apart from them, being distinguished from the other arts by certain features that cannot fail to determine our attitude
towards it. I shall begin by discussing these features, since a grasp of them will be essential to understanding later arguments, and since they will show what a frail and fragmentary thing is this concept of 'art' that we have inherited."

Scruton, Roger (1979) The Aesthetics pf Architecture. London: Matheuen & Co., pp 4, 5.

Wednesday, 8 September 2010

The true, the good and the beautiful (R. Scruton)

"There is an appealing idea about beauty which goes back to Plato and Plotinus, and which became incorporated by various routes into Christian Theological Thinking. According to this idea beauty is an ultimate value - something that we pursue for its own sake, and for the pursuit of which no further reason need to be given. Beauty should therefore be compared to truth and goodness, one member of a trio of ultimate values which justify our rational inclinations. Why believe p? Because it is true. Why want x? Because it is good. Why look at y? Because it is beautiful. In some was, philosophers have argued, those answers are on a par: each brings a state of mind into the ambit of reason, by connecting it to something that it is in our nature, as rational beings, to pursue. Someone who asked 'why believe what is true?' or 'why want what is good?' has failed to understand the nature of reasoning. He doesn't see that, if we are to justify our beliefs and desires at all, then our reasons must be anchored in the true and the good.

Does the same go for beauty? If someone asks me 'why are you interested in x?' is 'because it is beautiful' a final answer - one that is immune to counter-argument, like the answers 'because it is good', and 'because it is true'? To say as much is to overlook the subversive nature of beauty. Someone charmed by a myth mat be tempted to believe it: and in this case beauty is the enemy of truth. (Cf. Pindar: 'Beauty, which gives the myths acceptance, renders the incredible credible',First Olympian Ode.) A man attracted to a woman may be tempted to condone her vices: and in this case beauty is the enemy of goodness (Cf. L'Abbé Prévost, Manon Lescaut, which describes the moral ruin of the Chevalier des Grieux by the beautiful Manon.) Goodness and truth never compete, and the pursuit of the one is always compatible with a proper respect for the other. The pursuit of beauty, however, is far more questionable [...].

The status of beauty as an ultimate values is questionable, in the way that the status of truth and goodness are not. Let us at least say that this particular path to the understanding of beauty is not easily available to a modern thinker. The confidence with which philosophers once trod it is due to an assumption, made explicit already in the Enneads of Plotinus, that truth, beauty and goodness are attributes of the deity, ways in which the divine unity makes itself known to the human soul. That theological vision was edited for Christian use by St Thomas Aquinas, and embedded in the subtle and comprehensive reasoning for which that philosopher is justly famous. But it is not a vision that we can assume, and I propose for the time being to set it to one side, considering the concept of beauty without making any theological claims."

Scruton, Roger. Beauty. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009 (pp2-4).

Wednesday, 4 August 2010

Experiencia estética

"En las artes visuales el momento estético es ese instante fugaz, tan breve hasta ser casi sin tiempo, cuando el espectador es un todo con la obra de arte que está contemplando, o con la realidad de cualquier género que el espectador mismo ve en términos de arte, como son la forma y el color. [...] Ambos [sujeto y objeto] se convierten en una sola entidad: el tiempo y el espacio son abolidos, y el espectador está poseído de un único conocimiento. [...] el momento estético es un momento de visión mística."

Berenson, B. (1966) Estética e Historia en las Artes Visuales.
Fondo de Cultura Económica, México D.F. (p 86)


Una experiencia estética es independiente de las cualidades del objeto: no tiene ninguna relación con que éste nos guste o no, con que nos parezca bueno o malo, bello o desagradable. La experiencia estética es ese instante en el que sujeto y objeto se encuentran: el objeto produce algún tipo de reacción en el sujeto - favorable o desfavorable - que producirá un manifestarse con respecto a dicho objeto.

La experiencia estética conlleva una conexión, un vínculo, entre sujeto y objeto. Por lo tanto, podríamos decir que el antónimo de la experiencia estética es la indiferencia.



"Hay un elemento de pasión en toda percepción estético. Y sin embargo, cuando estamos sobrecogidos por la pasión, así como en momentos de extrema rabia, miedo, o celos, la experiencia es definitivamente no-estética. No hay relación sensible percibible entre las cualidades de la actividad que ha generado la pasión. [...] El proceso del arte en producción está relacionado con la estética [...]. Hasta que el artista esté satisfecho en su percepción con aquello que está haciendo, el continúa dando forma y volviendo a dar forma. La creación llega a su fin cuando su resultado es experimentado como bueno y esa experiencia viene no a través de mero juicio intelectual y externo, sino a través de la percepción directa. Un artista, en comparación con sus semejantes, es uno que no sólo está especialmente dotado con poderes para la ejecución, sino además con una sensibilidad inusual que también dirige sus obras y hechos."

Dewey, J. (2005) Art as Experience. Penguin, New York.


"Una persona está teniendo una experiencia estética durante un momento particular en el tiempo si, y sólo si la mayor parte de su actividad mental durante ese tiempo está unida y resulta (intensa, compleja y) disfrutable a través de su unión con la forma y las cualidades de un objeto determinado presentado de manera sensorial o imaginativa, y en el que su atención primaria está concentrada."

Beardsley; En: Dickie, G. (1974) "Beardsley's theory of Aesthetic Experience",
Journal of Aesthetic Education, Vol. VIII, Nº 2 (pp 13-23)
Related Posts with Thumbnails